The
Resurgence of Philistinism
The longstanding attempt to impose a moral paradigm on art
is evidence of a crisis in aesthetic meaning which seeks to discover common
rules and standards at the expense of subtlety and metaphor. The problems with
such an approach are myriad, but at their most significant represent an effort
to whitewash cultural expression by inserting its varied and heterogeneous
products into a narrowly defined and sanitized set of well labeled containers. These
receptacles are organized, often unwittingly, by levels of moral
intervention—whose political orientations can be situated almost anywhere on
the narrowly defined ideological spectrum lurking behind most value-specific
discourses—and stress didactic codes of collective and individual ethical
behavior consistent with popular conceptions of social equity and the restraint
of unacceptable impulses. Yet, it is the imposition of such an overtly
restrictive way of speaking about art, no matter how diffusely it is
applied—mostly the result of conversations both written and verbal taking place
within the more specialized areas of the culture industry, although it has
always had a populist corollary in so-called public-discourse—that constrains
and deforms the way it is perceived.
The most predominant form that such parsing of value in art
has taken is peculiar in that it is not overtly concerned with morality, but rather
with what is often referred to as problems in ‘craft’ or ‘mastery.’ The
conception of these aforementioned characteristics is influenced by definitions
derived from an almost anachronistic conception of ‘naturalism’ culled primarily
from classical painting and sculpture. These forms are equated with supposedly
value-neutral categories of ‘quality’ and ‘excellence’ of which most
contemporary aesthetic productions are believed to be lacking. The assumption here,
that approaches to form are somehow synonymous with normally evaluative issues
of quality, presents the often restrictive normative standards that such
discourse imposes on art as inevitable and universally transparent. And, while
it isn’t inherently ‘value specific’ in its conception of the ‘ethics of art,’ it
uses a similarly constructed aesthetic framework to address questions of import
and value, often confusing the latter with superficial assessments of stylistic criterion that
privilege idealized and familiar forms over any sort of ‘self-indulgent’
experimentalism. Within this framework, the language of utility provides the
superficial imprimatur of legitimacy to cloak arguments that are essentially
attacks against the unconventional.
The problem with this approach is precisely its tendency to
ascribe any kind of innovation to self-indulgence’—a generic catchphrase for any
work whose conception, themes or materials are too novel, nuanced, or abstruse
for the attachment of generalized sentiments regarding ‘feeling,’ or ‘meaning,’
or ‘quality.’ I do not enumerate this style of ascribing significance to
isolate or make fun of it—these are, after all, fundamental ways that people
make sense of the aesthetic—but I do wish to make a distinction between the
tendency to assume that these are totalizing concepts, as opposed to a more
complex understanding of how aesthetic presentations manipulate, effect and
engage individuals. The notion of ascribing definite value—as if one were
looking at something necessitating an almost empirical reduction into constrained
categories and levels of appreciation—is invariably mistaken for the more
multifaceted process of ‘beholding.’
This subjective and qualitative ‘beholding,’ which is
amongst the most primary and essential aspects of seeing an artwork, in any
form, has been referred to by the critic Lucy Lippard as “The Erotics of
Engagement.” Such ‘erotics’ are not necessarily sexual, but sensual and
engrossing, and owe much of their potential to transfix one’s attention to
their unusual pedigree, which derives originally from the visceral qualities of
the transcendent religious gaze. This way of understanding phenomenon outside
the linguistic and conceptual boundaries of daily society’s more utilitarian rituals,
is inseparable in many ways from that uncanny and nameless sense of
interconnectedness and mystery often inspired by spiritual evocation.
However, as this very aspect of aesthetics was secularized
long ago, the utilitarian ethos predominant in western culture orients various
interpretive strata towards pragmatic considerations of use-value. Since ‘Art’
is not conceived to be ‘useful,’ in any ordinary sense, the confusion generated
by the desire to ascribe a graspable meaning to a work of art, often leads to
this very form of misattribution. The resulting leveling—an outgrowth of the
subtle reification involved in transposing the aesthetic with the practical, so
that the former can be more easily categorized within a known agglomeration of
taxa—fossilizes art by replacing its organic constituents with a molecular
aggregation of more easily grasped quanta. This quanta is the secretion from
that aforesaid reification process, which invariably hardens into readymade
clichés, themselves honeycombed with a largely irrelevant series of pragmatic
prerequisites of aesthetic value. The categories that grow out of such
practices, misrepresent the aesthetic by essentially placing it in the same
category as aluminum siding, kitchen wallpaper and even something as specific as the effectiveness of
snow plows during a winter storm—all materially based objects and practices,
whose aesthetic qualities are subordinate to their usefulness and
appropriateness within certain functional environments. This is, on the face of
it, an absurd misrepresentation of the aesthetic, as art does not perform
work—at least not in the ordinary sense—is not conceived as an instrument of a
larger apparatus or function; and, with the occasional exception of
architecture, is not created for the sake of utility.
Art exists largely for its own sake, and loses its
self-contained integrity when subordinated to another purpose. This assertion
at first seems like the preface to a manifesto of self-indulgence, and would
surely anger those who believe that art should ‘enlighten’—in the sense of
‘educating’ viewers. The latter notion would cover the entire spectrum of
‘politicized’ art from the puerile simplicities inherent in The Book of Virtues, to the political agit-prop
of the more didactic forms of ‘activist-art.’ The problem with such work is not
so much its subordination of form to ideology—certainly a difficult proposition
in an aesthetic production, as it tends to freeze the work in the contextual
amber of topicality—as its surrender to the didactic ethos of pedagogy. Once
the intention to teach has been transformed into aesthetic action, the
aspirations of the work become utilitarian and self-limiting. Art, because it
is based around metaphors, is ineluctably transformed into a different
organism—at worst a platform for catechism—when used to frame lessons and
specific ideas. As an instrument utilized to achieve tangible ends, it shrinks
proportionately to the size of the concrete and literal-minded dimensions of
simple sloganeering and exhortation.
Cousin to this tendency is the practice of framing art
within moral parameters. This approach is often packaged as purpose-oriented,
and favors arguments that contextualize aesthetic production as something which
should enlighten and exalt. At its most extreme, these critical polemics insist
that art must elevate the soul while providing a workable paradigm of values. Aside
from the fact that conceptual tropes such as ‘the soul’ are mystifications of
the self, the idea that art should be uplifting is a commonplace
sentimentalization, often utilized by artists in various contexts, that
disguises the frequently brutal and amoral forms intrinsic to many historically
revered aesthetic productions.
The desire to frame, and provide closure by dressing
difficult work in the judge’s robes of moral didacticism has a long history in
American popular culture. This tendency is vividly illustrated in both early
pulp literature dating back to the nineteenth century, and the structuring of
anti-vice films from the 1930’s, whose appeal was primarily based on the very seductions
that they were ostensibly produced to warn people against. Of course, the
moralistic framing of lurid details, in drug and sex films—later seen in pulp comic
strips, themselves influenced by the ‘dime-novels’ of the previous century—was
an obligatory inoculation against the criticism that such forms were inherently
subversive. A more common approach, not necessarily confined to the tricky
terrain of self-conscious marketing, is often seen in commercial cinema, when
auteurs explain their own work in terms appropriate for moral parables. The
Hughes brothers, for example, reacted to strong criticism of their
ground-breaking Ghetto-Verite
masterpiece, Menace II Society, by
citing, in an interview segment provided in the film’s video release, an
underlying moral architecture framed around a principle character whose
criminality eventually leads to his violent downfall. This lesson in the
liabilities of incorrigible behavior is made explicit in the film’s final
scene, when Caine rhetorically comments on the misguided nature of his cavalier
attitude towards crime and violence.
Such built-in explanatory structures are common,
particularly in domestic cinema; and, are used to contextualize the often
blatant acts of violence—both unprovoked and in self-defense—presented on
screen in such powerful fashion in films like Goodfellas, Casino, Hamburger Hill, and even Saving Private Ryan. The strategies
employed within the structures of these and other movies are specific to their
individual plot-lines, narratives and audience expectations. Thus, in Martin
Scorsese’s morally complex universe, the gangsters themselves frame the action
with over-dubbed narratives that provide the ironic contrast of hindsight to
accompany the sensuous and violent actions highlighting the films. In sharp
contrast, Steven Spielberg frames the innovative intimacy and physicality,
which heighten the moral ambiguity of films such as Munich and Lincoln, with
introductory remarks designed to pre-emptively respond to criticism, while
circumscribing his narratives with a moral clarity not always available within
the ethical-corridors of various geographies and historical periods. This
common form of ex-post facto moral gerrymandering is largely an attempt to
preempt the most obvious criticisms of the cinematic portrayal of libertine
excess, but far from the most frequent.
The critical aperture of moral opprobrium is both the most
pervasive and least subtle of the qualities that characterize the resurgence of
philistinism in aesthetic criticism. Admittedly, this quality is more visible
in the world of pop-culture analysis and amongst those ordinarily predisposed
to avoid anything that might garner the formal appellation of ‘Art.’ Nonetheless,
it can be encountered, in its various guises, in museums, journals, and blogs—
of course—as well as within the discourses of activist politics. It is also
quite prominently displayed in the often self-righteous discourse on African
American musical culture, particularly Hip-Hop music which has achieved
prominence because of its often garish honesty and its linguistic
inventiveness. Both, of course, have played a role in its demonization by an
assortment of Church and civic leaders, as well as politicians and other
would-be guardians of public morality. However, Hip-Hop’s Chutzpah is only one
of its many supposed transgressions against good taste and morality; and,
moreover, it is only the latest African American cultural form to be accused of
such slights against the larger culture. In fact, both blues and jazz were, in
their’ time tarred with a similar brush by the establishment of the Baptist
church and even the NAACP, who saw these forms in terms of the degradation of
the image of their respective communities. Similarly, Rap Music is often cited
for its violent lyrics, blatantly sexual content and grisly realism—all of
which, with the possible exception of the latter, although it is often quite
grisly, are actually considered obligatory elements in most operas—but these
are qualities that have grown out of the longstanding cultural practice of
‘Signifying’ also known as ‘Playing the Dozens, ‘ whose provenance stems back
to the early days of slavery, and certain practices seen in slave auctions. As
with many cultural adaptations, these methods of accommodation and personal
affirmation were both inventive and empowering, and have provided a template
into which Hip Hop is merely the latest successor.
Part of the reason for why older forms become acceptable as
newer innovations are subject to the bulk of such familiar moral and aesthetic
criticisms, is attributable to the way age confers antique status upon various
styles of cultural expression. Even more importantly, however, is that changing
social contexts make visible certain gaps in the narrative and structural conventions
of any art-form—often more difficult to discern when such stylistic innovations
are initially received within a given cultural sensibility—lessening the
appearance of verisimility, and conversely, making it more acceptable as a
result of this perceived inauthenticity; often complicated by its sentimental
resurrection as a true-essence or cultural voice. This is as much a reflection
of a failure to acknowledge culture’s inherent and vital level of artifice, as
it is a misreading of aesthetic production as a form of ethicized moral
reflection. In fact, it is the former which shapes and adapts the latter,
usually without regard to the hierarchical teleology intrinsic to popular
notions of moral development.
Works such as Delacroix’s Raft of the Medusa, Gericault’s Wreck
of the Hesperias, and Giovanni Bologna’s Rape of the Sabine Woman, are only three of an innumerable array of
western artworks whose use of images
from antiquity eroticize and sensationalize violence by fetishizing its
effects—a tendency that also illuminates the intricacies of various forms of
suffering and transgression. This is not an aesthetic criticism as these are
works of penetrating vision and impeccable technique; but, frank
acknowledgement of one of the often overlooked functions of art, particularly
during the centuries preceding the Enlightenment: namely, facilitating the
prominence of the phallocentric gaze. This ‘gaze’ was certainly evident in the
sensuality of many works across the centuries—such as Bernini’s Ecstasy of Saint Theresa, for example.
However, its inherent eroticism is most famously on display in one of the first
paintings to confront and challenge that gaze, Manet’s Luncheon on the Grass; whose reclining nude—offset, as was typical
of such paintings, by clothed, and hence, empowered male figures—looks back
with a penetrating frankness at the viewer. Such indelicacies were major
artistic scandals of the time, precisely because they questioned predominant
attitudes regarding sexuality and cultural subordination; but, they were
presented as transgressions against “decency’ and “good taste.” The fact that
neither of the latter two animals has had much input into the vagaries and
vicissitudes of human relations or the development of culture—except as covert
and disingenuous ways of perpetuating certain forms of ideological and social
hegemony—has often been overlooked by both official, and self-styled, moralists.
One should not confuse an inherently phallocentric framework
with the notion that western art is therefore sensationalistic and shallow.
Rather, these qualities reflect the innate aspects of the discourse in which
such works are embedded, and do not foreclose on the possibility of a profound
exploration of the human condition. In fact, much of the substance of these
works reveals that, while the tendency to evaluate an object morally may imply
a separation between the aforesaid qualities, they are often inextricably
intertwined. An artwork, is a culmination of a particular vision rendered at a
particular historical moment by a specific sensibility, and is, thus, a
combination of many qualities; to parse them out separately, is to artificially
break them down into discrete analytical categories that do not explain or
necessarily enhance one’s understanding of a work. It is therefore important to
take the holistic quality of these aesthetic artifacts into account before
attempting to reconcile them to a particular moral or ethical position in
reference to subject matter and portrayal.
An example of this holistic quality can be found in the work
of Michelangelo, whose paintings and sculpture seamlessly combine the immediate
sensuality of eroticism with a transcendent and organically unified moral
vision. One may, at first, wonder if such a concatenation of qualities can
exist within any individual work simultaneously. The problem however, is not in
the unified nature of aesthetic production, but in the fragmented system of
categories which western reason imposes upon it; thus, the notion that art must
either be morally unified—and perhaps even didactic—or saturated by eroticism
and excess, is a false dichotomy: Instead, aesthetic works contain various
elements that are often ambiguous. This is clearly illustrated in the forms of
Michelangelo’s most famous works, such as his robust, marble, David, and his
figures on the walls and ceiling of the Sistine Chapel. The religious and
humanistic nature of his informing vision is clearly obvious, as is the
inherent sensuality of these images. This sort of eroticism need not be located
personally as a manifestation of some discrete idiosyncratic quality which the
artist separately infuses into his work. Instead—and particularly in contrast
to Freud’s reductive reading of the Chapel ceiling, which ignores the
conventions of early sixteenth century Italian art, and locates the
significance of Michelangelo’s figures in his supposed, and largely irrelevant,
homosexuality—the work is of a piece, indivisible into separately conceived
thematic and symbolic components unless one imposes an artificial paradigm
whose results would largely reflect its own compartmentalized structure. Thus,
the tendency of historians to break these works into discretely anatomized
parcels creates the artifact of essentialized “meaning,” mistakenly assumed to
be a transparent reflection of the observer’s own inquiry.
The thematic coherence seen in cultural artifacts of diverse
types—including western art, up until the middle of the nineteenth century—is a
product of a relatively unified metaphysical viewpoint. This should not be
equated with a vision of cultural harmony, but with the existence of more
prevalent master narratives. Once the culture of the enlightenment succeeded in
fractioning the very perception of such a world into discrete analytical
compartments, aesthetic production gradually became alienated from its own
sources of traditional inspiration; a factor which was incorporated, as a new
and disturbing form of knowledge, into the aesthetic process as well. The subsequent
restructuring of reality, inspired by the works of Descartes, Linnaeus, Freud,
and Marx, amongst others, fragmented western perceptions into parameters which
created strong resistance through their systematic denial of the primal
realities that had always informed the wellsprings of art. Hence, artists, now
freed from various overriding aesthetic and ideological conventions, explored
these new ironies through an expanded and innovative approach to meaning and
form.
This subsequent fracturing of aesthetic unities also
inspired a resurgence of the desire to morally recuperate the past through a
return to what were popularly conceived of as the eternal verities of the
‘masters.’ This privileging of the naturalistic conventions of Renaissance art,
as the ‘true’ epitome of aesthetics, was based on a subtle mistaking of the
supposed truths represented by illusionism, and its strict rules of mimeses,
with the moral certainties attributed to a past era retrospectively
characterized as having a seamless metaphysical unity. The gradual
transmutation of this manifestation of ethicized nostalgia into a set of often
reductive casuistic principles, to be applied equally in all areas of
contemporary life, has become an institutionalized aspect of the ongoing
discourse about art in the western world. This enhanced version of a familiar
one-size-fits all approach to criticism, is prevalent in all of the performing
and fine arts, although the sophistication of the actual arguments vary widely.
It also bears repeating that this super-imposing of a moralistic framework is
not ideologically unified—as merely the province of the religious right, or
cultural conservatives—but is dispersed across the political and social
spectrum; and, has become even more diffuse as its basic assumptions have been
subsequently adopted by a heterogeneous assortment of variously positioned
individuals and organizations.
As such it has not restricted itself to contextual
representations of diverse approaches to ‘morality,’ across the spectrum of the
arts themselves, but has also complicated the already byzantine analysis of the
inherently anachronistic world of high-scale art patrons, collectors and
investors. It is important to bear in mind that the market value of art is not
a reflection of aesthetic value, but rather the result of the often
self-contained nature of the world of artists and collectors, which has reacted
to the rapid shifts in both the technological applications used in aesthetic
production and the often self-referential sophistication of contemporary
conceptual paradigms. The resulting tendency, to fetishize anything that
appears to bear the imprimatur of the ‘artist,’ often results in exponential
increases in the value of such works. This does not necessarily reflect badly
on the work in question, it merely implies an almost desperate predisposition
amongst art collectors to read grandiose gestures into works whose subtleties
tend to conceal such anachronistic intimations of grandeur. Thus, anything that
even appears to commune on such hallowed epic ground—with allowances made to
ostensibly take into account newer and more complex conceptual approaches—is
often the focus of art-world hysteria, even though such reactions tend to be
short lived. Nonetheless, they can rapidly increase the monetary value of the
artwork in question. This has led some moralistically inclined critics and
observers to find the fault within the work rather than in the machinations of
the art-world’s somewhat antediluvian system of patronage and private
financing. This is a classic case of blaming the artist for the idiosyncratic
economics of the culture of art collectors, which spins on its own peculiar
axis and resonates to a separate, albeit tangentially related, rhythm from that
which regulates the metabolic fluxions of the collective realm of the artists
themselves.
One example of how this blame game works can be found in the
controversy over Andres Serrano and his by now notorious photograph of a
crucifix soaked in urine, aptly named, Piss
Christ. In 1989, this widely misunderstood photograph became a galvanizing
exhibit in the far right’s philippic against funding for supposedly “immoral”
art. In a letter originally published by the Richmond News Leader—and reprinted in C. Carr’s, One Edge: Performance at the end of the
Twentieth Century—in March 1989, an angry reader criticized The Virginia
Museum for displaying and promoting the work:
The
Virginia Museum should not be in the business of
promoting
and subsidizing hatred and intolerance…
Would
they pay the kkk to do work defaming blacks?
Would
they display a Jewish symbol under urine?
Has
Christianity become fair game in our society
for
any kind of blasphemy and slander?” [p-285]
The irony of this missive is that the artist in question
used his funding to underwrite a series of profoundly disquieting, and yet
moving, photographs of North Carolina Klansman in full regalia—and later,
without their hoods. While this may, initially, appear to reinforce the
letter’s content, it was the way in which the humanity of the photographer’s
subjects and his desire to capture it through their masks, projected compassion
rather than prejudice which sets these photos apart from mere propaganda. This
is more obvious, when one realizes that Serrano is a gay person of color, whose
desire to explore the common humanity in all people transcends even these
differences. This exhibit was interspersed with pictures taken of homeless New
Yorkers—a theme he has more recently returned to, showcasing various panhandling
signs in his latest project—to emphasize both the humanity and the moral
diversity of the dispossessed and marginal. That no one would have anticipated
such a follow up to his critique of organized religion is a testament to both
the creativity and inherent humanism of art; and the way that its often forward
thinking, paradigm violating portrayals function counter-intuitively to make
new observations about seemingly familiar things.
One might accuse Serrano—in light of the political nature of
the Piss Christ photograph—of
subordinating content to politics. In this case, however, the distinction would
be an artificial one, as the theme of the work is integrated with its
presentation into an organic whole. This is no mere attempt at post-hoc
justification but recognition of the way that political art—of any ideological
stripe—is distinct from political art that subordinates content to message. The
issue, of course, is the level of didactic content, and how well the work
resolves as an organic entity. This would also apply to older moralistic works
such as David’s Oath of the Horatii,
and Death of Socrates, both are
political paintings promoting a set of idealized qualities, yet seamlessly
integrated without noticeable cant. One might suggest that such qualities are
in the eye of the beholder, which is true in the abstract sense; but, any
perusal of Western art produced during the last two millennia quickly reveals
the difference between morally infused work and aesthetic production acting as
a handmaiden to a specific message. The latter tends towards an extreme
narrowness of vision, is rarely transcendent (although it may privilege
transcendental values), and quickly tarnishes with age.
That those inclined to make snap judgments by virtue of an
ideologically induced tunnel vision might miss the broad diversity of an
artist’s vision is not surprising. It is a sad testimonial however, to a lack
of imagination, particularly on the part of moral conservatives who seem to
conceive of intent and scope in rigidly circumscribed terms that do not allow
for the possibility of a more catholic diversity of choices and tangents. This
is certainly not confined to those on the right; but their frequent lack of any
awareness of causality, makes their objections seem narrower than those of
their also rigidly ideological counterparts of the liberal left. Of course, in
neither case does the criticism transcend an equally restrictive moral
casuistry, that when applied to aesthetics gives way to an unremarked upon
tendency towards familiar catechisms.
In both cases part of the confusion arises from the idea
that art should enhance humanity by essentially ennobling people and cultural
practices. This is a longstanding fiction, as laudatory as it is invalid, which
any quick perusal of an operatic libretto will usually make clear.
Unfortunately, it has spawned a diverse array of moralistic progeny that
function similarly to a collectively expressed and historically prevalent
anxiety towards the unconventional. And, regardless of how it cloaks itself—or
of how heartfelt some of its instinctual recoiling may appear to its
advocates—it smacks of the advance guard of a familiar form of reactive
authoritarianism; one now wearing the updated vestments of the new guardians of
cultural decency, even when they purport to reflect the values of fair
mindedness. One must remember, of course, that order and restriction always has
the appearance of a silver lining—which gleams like a brightly reflective pair
of handcuffs, and that presents its essentially inhibitory circumspectness as a
form of utopianism. When faced with such direct assaults on our collective
rights, as people and practitioners of culture, to be contrary, divergent, or
even solipsistic— especially when it concerns artists, whether they are recognized
officially or not—we should remember the words of Andre Breton, who was
referring to an overall seismic shift in culture more far reaching than any
single manifestation of aesthetics, when he said:
“Art will be convulsive, or it will not be at all.”
JZRothstein (first completed draft) 1/25/2014
No comments:
Post a Comment